Gauss•AVCTORE CAROLO FRIDERICO GAVSS HELMSTADII APVD C. G. FLECKEISEN. 1799
Abbo Floriacensis1 work
Abelard3 works
Addison9 works
Adso Dervensis1 work
Aelredus Rievallensis1 work
Alanus de Insulis2 works
Albert of Aix1 work
HISTORIA HIEROSOLYMITANAE EXPEDITIONIS12 sections
Albertano of Brescia5 works
DE AMORE ET DILECTIONE DEI4 sections
SERMONES4 sections
Alcuin9 works
Alfonsi1 work
Ambrose4 works
Ambrosius4 works
Ammianus1 work
Ampelius1 work
Andrea da Bergamo1 work
Andreas Capellanus1 work
DE AMORE LIBRI TRES3 sections
Annales Regni Francorum1 work
Annales Vedastini1 work
Annales Xantenses1 work
Anonymus Neveleti1 work
Anonymus Valesianus2 works
Apicius1 work
DE RE COQUINARIA5 sections
Appendix Vergiliana1 work
Apuleius2 works
METAMORPHOSES12 sections
DE DOGMATE PLATONIS6 sections
Aquinas6 works
Archipoeta1 work
Arnobius1 work
ADVERSVS NATIONES LIBRI VII7 sections
Arnulf of Lisieux1 work
Asconius1 work
Asserius1 work
Augustine5 works
CONFESSIONES13 sections
DE CIVITATE DEI23 sections
DE TRINITATE15 sections
CONTRA SECUNDAM IULIANI RESPONSIONEM2 sections
Augustus1 work
RES GESTAE DIVI AVGVSTI2 sections
Aurelius Victor1 work
LIBER ET INCERTORVM LIBRI3 sections
Ausonius2 works
Avianus1 work
Avienus2 works
Bacon3 works
HISTORIA REGNI HENRICI SEPTIMI REGIS ANGLIAE11 sections
Balde2 works
Baldo1 work
Bebel1 work
Bede2 works
HISTORIAM ECCLESIASTICAM GENTIS ANGLORUM7 sections
Benedict1 work
Berengar1 work
Bernard of Clairvaux1 work
Bernard of Cluny1 work
DE CONTEMPTU MUNDI LIBRI DUO2 sections
Biblia Sacra3 works
VETUS TESTAMENTUM49 sections
NOVUM TESTAMENTUM27 sections
Bigges1 work
Boethius de Dacia2 works
Bonaventure1 work
Breve Chronicon Northmannicum1 work
Buchanan1 work
Bultelius2 works
Caecilius Balbus1 work
Caesar3 works
COMMENTARIORUM LIBRI VII DE BELLO GALLICO CUM A. HIRTI SUPPLEMENTO8 sections
COMMENTARIORUM LIBRI III DE BELLO CIVILI3 sections
LIBRI INCERTORUM AUCTORUM3 sections
Calpurnius Flaccus1 work
Calpurnius Siculus1 work
Campion8 works
Carmen Arvale1 work
Carmen de Martyrio1 work
Carmen in Victoriam1 work
Carmen Saliare1 work
Carmina Burana1 work
Cassiodorus5 works
Catullus1 work
Censorinus1 work
Christian Creeds1 work
Cicero3 works
ORATORIA33 sections
PHILOSOPHIA21 sections
EPISTULAE4 sections
Cinna Helvius1 work
Claudian4 works
Claudii Oratio1 work
Claudius Caesar1 work
Columbus1 work
Columella2 works
Commodianus3 works
Conradus Celtis2 works
Constitutum Constantini1 work
Contemporary9 works
Cotta1 work
Dante4 works
Dares the Phrygian1 work
de Ave Phoenice1 work
De Expugnatione Terrae Sanctae per Saladinum1 work
Declaratio Arbroathis1 work
Decretum Gelasianum1 work
Descartes1 work
Dies Irae1 work
Disticha Catonis1 work
Egeria1 work
ITINERARIUM PEREGRINATIO2 sections
Einhard1 work
Ennius1 work
Epistolae Austrasicae1 work
Epistulae de Priapismo1 work
Erasmus7 works
Erchempert1 work
Eucherius1 work
Eugippius1 work
Eutropius1 work
BREVIARIVM HISTORIAE ROMANAE10 sections
Exurperantius1 work
Fabricius Montanus1 work
Falcandus1 work
Falcone di Benevento1 work
Ficino1 work
Fletcher1 work
Florus1 work
EPITOME DE T. LIVIO BELLORUM OMNIUM ANNORUM DCC LIBRI DUO2 sections
Foedus Aeternum1 work
Forsett2 works
Fredegarius1 work
Frodebertus & Importunus1 work
Frontinus3 works
STRATEGEMATA4 sections
DE AQUAEDUCTU URBIS ROMAE2 sections
OPUSCULA RERUM RUSTICARUM4 sections
Fulgentius3 works
MITOLOGIARUM LIBRI TRES3 sections
Gaius4 works
Galileo1 work
Garcilaso de la Vega1 work
Gaudeamus Igitur1 work
Gellius1 work
Germanicus1 work
Gesta Francorum10 works
Gesta Romanorum1 work
Gioacchino da Fiore1 work
Godfrey of Winchester2 works
Grattius1 work
Gregorii Mirabilia Urbis Romae1 work
Gregorius Magnus1 work
Gregory IX5 works
Gregory of Tours1 work
LIBRI HISTORIARUM10 sections
Gregory the Great1 work
Gregory VII1 work
Gwinne8 works
Henry of Settimello1 work
Henry VII1 work
Historia Apolloni1 work
Historia Augusta30 works
Historia Brittonum1 work
Holberg1 work
Horace3 works
SERMONES2 sections
CARMINA4 sections
EPISTULAE5 sections
Hugo of St. Victor2 works
Hydatius2 works
Hyginus3 works
Hymni1 work
Hymni et cantica1 work
Iacobus de Voragine1 work
LEGENDA AUREA24 sections
Ilias Latina1 work
Iordanes2 works
Isidore of Seville3 works
ETYMOLOGIARVM SIVE ORIGINVM LIBRI XX20 sections
SENTENTIAE LIBRI III3 sections
Iulius Obsequens1 work
Iulius Paris1 work
Ius Romanum4 works
Janus Secundus2 works
Johann H. Withof1 work
Johann P. L. Withof1 work
Johannes de Alta Silva1 work
Johannes de Plano Carpini1 work
John of Garland1 work
Jordanes2 works
Julius Obsequens1 work
Junillus1 work
Justin1 work
HISTORIARVM PHILIPPICARVM T. POMPEII TROGI LIBRI XLIV IN EPITOMEN REDACTI46 sections
Justinian3 works
INSTITVTIONES5 sections
CODEX12 sections
DIGESTA50 sections
Juvenal1 work
Kepler1 work
Landor4 works
Laurentius Corvinus2 works
Legenda Regis Stephani1 work
Leo of Naples1 work
HISTORIA DE PRELIIS ALEXANDRI MAGNI3 sections
Leo the Great1 work
SERMONES DE QUADRAGESIMA2 sections
Liber Kalilae et Dimnae1 work
Liber Pontificalis1 work
Livius Andronicus1 work
Livy1 work
AB VRBE CONDITA LIBRI37 sections
Lotichius1 work
Lucan1 work
DE BELLO CIVILI SIVE PHARSALIA10 sections
Lucretius1 work
DE RERVM NATVRA LIBRI SEX6 sections
Lupus Protospatarius Barensis1 work
Macarius of Alexandria1 work
Macarius the Great1 work
Magna Carta1 work
Maidstone1 work
Malaterra1 work
DE REBUS GESTIS ROGERII CALABRIAE ET SICILIAE COMITIS ET ROBERTI GUISCARDI DUCIS FRATRIS EIUS4 sections
Manilius1 work
ASTRONOMICON5 sections
Marbodus Redonensis1 work
Marcellinus Comes2 works
Martial1 work
Martin of Braga13 works
Marullo1 work
Marx1 work
Maximianus1 work
May1 work
SUPPLEMENTUM PHARSALIAE8 sections
Melanchthon4 works
Milton1 work
Minucius Felix1 work
Mirabilia Urbis Romae1 work
Mirandola1 work
CARMINA9 sections
Miscellanea Carminum42 works
Montanus1 work
Naevius1 work
Navagero1 work
Nemesianus1 work
ECLOGAE4 sections
Nepos3 works
LIBER DE EXCELLENTIBUS DVCIBUS EXTERARVM GENTIVM24 sections
Newton1 work
PHILOSOPHIÆ NATURALIS PRINCIPIA MATHEMATICA4 sections
Nithardus1 work
HISTORIARUM LIBRI QUATTUOR4 sections
Notitia Dignitatum2 works
Novatian1 work
Origo gentis Langobardorum1 work
Orosius1 work
HISTORIARUM ADVERSUM PAGANOS LIBRI VII7 sections
Otto of Freising1 work
GESTA FRIDERICI IMPERATORIS5 sections
Ovid7 works
METAMORPHOSES15 sections
AMORES3 sections
HEROIDES21 sections
ARS AMATORIA3 sections
TRISTIA5 sections
EX PONTO4 sections
Owen1 work
Papal Bulls4 works
Pascoli5 works
Passerat1 work
Passio Perpetuae1 work
Patricius1 work
Tome I: Panaugia2 sections
Paulinus Nolensis1 work
Paulus Diaconus4 works
Persius1 work
Pervigilium Veneris1 work
Petronius2 works
Petrus Blesensis1 work
Petrus de Ebulo1 work
Phaedrus2 works
FABVLARVM AESOPIARVM LIBRI QVINQVE5 sections
Phineas Fletcher1 work
Planctus destructionis1 work
Plautus21 works
Pliny the Younger2 works
EPISTVLARVM LIBRI DECEM10 sections
Poggio Bracciolini1 work
Pomponius Mela1 work
DE CHOROGRAPHIA3 sections
Pontano1 work
Poree1 work
Porphyrius1 work
Precatio Terrae1 work
Priapea1 work
Professio Contra Priscillianum1 work
Propertius1 work
ELEGIAE4 sections
Prosperus3 works
Prudentius2 works
Pseudoplatonica12 works
Publilius Syrus1 work
Quintilian2 works
INSTITUTIONES12 sections
Raoul of Caen1 work
Regula ad Monachos1 work
Reposianus1 work
Ricardi de Bury1 work
Richerus1 work
HISTORIARUM LIBRI QUATUOR4 sections
Rimbaud1 work
Ritchie's Fabulae Faciles1 work
Roman Epitaphs1 work
Roman Inscriptions1 work
Ruaeus1 work
Ruaeus' Aeneid1 work
Rutilius Lupus1 work
Rutilius Namatianus1 work
Sabinus1 work
EPISTULAE TRES AD OVIDIANAS EPISTULAS RESPONSORIAE3 sections
Sallust10 works
Sannazaro2 works
Scaliger1 work
Sedulius2 works
CARMEN PASCHALE5 sections
Seneca9 works
EPISTULAE MORALES AD LUCILIUM16 sections
QUAESTIONES NATURALES7 sections
DE CONSOLATIONE3 sections
DE IRA3 sections
DE BENEFICIIS3 sections
DIALOGI7 sections
FABULAE8 sections
Septem Sapientum1 work
Sidonius Apollinaris2 works
Sigebert of Gembloux3 works
Silius Italicus1 work
Solinus2 works
DE MIRABILIBUS MUNDI Mommsen 1st edition (1864)4 sections
DE MIRABILIBUS MUNDI C.L.F. Panckoucke edition (Paris 1847)4 sections
Spinoza1 work
Statius3 works
THEBAID12 sections
ACHILLEID2 sections
Stephanus de Varda1 work
Suetonius2 works
Sulpicia1 work
Sulpicius Severus2 works
CHRONICORUM LIBRI DUO2 sections
Syrus1 work
Tacitus5 works
Terence6 works
Tertullian32 works
Testamentum Porcelli1 work
Theodolus1 work
Theodosius16 works
Theophanes1 work
Thomas à Kempis1 work
DE IMITATIONE CHRISTI4 sections
Thomas of Edessa1 work
Tibullus1 work
TIBVLLI ALIORVMQUE CARMINVM LIBRI TRES3 sections
Tünger1 work
Valerius Flaccus1 work
Valerius Maximus1 work
FACTORVM ET DICTORVM MEMORABILIVM LIBRI NOVEM9 sections
Vallauri1 work
Varro2 works
RERVM RVSTICARVM DE AGRI CVLTURA3 sections
DE LINGVA LATINA7 sections
Vegetius1 work
EPITOMA REI MILITARIS LIBRI IIII4 sections
Velleius Paterculus1 work
HISTORIAE ROMANAE2 sections
Venantius Fortunatus1 work
Vico1 work
Vida1 work
Vincent of Lérins1 work
Virgil3 works
AENEID12 sections
ECLOGUES10 sections
GEORGICON4 sections
Vita Agnetis1 work
Vita Caroli IV1 work
Vita Sancti Columbae2 works
Vitruvius1 work
DE ARCHITECTVRA10 sections
Waardenburg1 work
Waltarius3 works
Walter Mapps2 works
Walter of Châtillon1 work
William of Apulia1 work
William of Conches2 works
William of Tyre1 work
HISTORIA RERUM IN PARTIBUS TRANSMARINIS GESTARUM24 sections
Xylander1 work
Zonaras1 work
Quaelibet aequatio algebraica determinata reduci potest ad formam xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2+ etc. +M=0, ita vt m sit numerus integer positiuus. Si partem primam huius aequationis per X denotamus, aequationique X=0 per plures valores inaequales ipsius x satisfieri supponimus, puta ponendo x=α, x=β, x=γ etc.
Any determined algebraic equation can be reduced to the form xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2+ etc. +M=0, so that m is a positive integer number. If we denote the first part of this equation by X, and suppose that the equation X=0 is satisfied for several unequal values of x itself, for example by setting x=α, x=β, x=γ etc.
measures the function X: the equation X=0 will be satisfied by making x equal to any of the quantities α, β, γ etc. Finally, if X is equal to a product of m such simple factors (whether all are different, or some of them identical), other simple factors besides these will not be able to measure the function X. Wherefore an equation of the mth degree cannot have more than m roots; yet at the same time it is evident that an equation of the mth degree can have fewer roots, even if X is resoluble into m simple factors: for if among these factors some are identical, the multitude of different modes of satisfying the equation will necessarily be less than m. Nevertheless, for the sake of concinnity, geometers have preferred to say that the equation in this case too has m roots, and that only certain of them turn out equal among themselves: which of course they could permit themselves.
Quae hucusque sunt enarrata, in libris algebraicis sufficienter demonstrantur neque rigorem geometricum vspiam offendunt. Sed nimis praepropere et sine praeuia demonstratione solida adoptauisse videntur analystae theorema cui tota fere doctrina aequationum superstructa est: Quamuis functionem talem vt X semper in m factores simplices resolui posse, siue hoc quod cum illo prorsus conspirat, quamuis aequationem mti gradus reuera habere m radices. Quum iam in aequationibus secundi gradus saepissime ad tales casus perueniatur, qui theoremati huic repugnant: algebraistae, vt hos illi subiicerent, coacti fuerunt, fingere quantitatem quandam imaginariam cuius quadratum sit -1, et tum agnouerunt, si quantitates formae a+b√-1 perinde concedantur vt reales, theorema non modo pro aequationibus secundi gradus verum esse, sed etiam pro cubicis et biquadraticis.
The things that have been set forth thus far are sufficiently demonstrated in algebraic books and nowhere offend geometric rigor. But the analysts seem to have adopted too hastily and without a prior solid demonstration the theorem upon which almost the whole doctrine of equations is superstructured: that any function such that X can always be resolved into m simple factors, or this, which entirely agrees with it, that any equation of the mth degree truly has m roots. Since even in equations of the second degree one very often comes upon cases that conflict with this theorem, the algebraists, in order to bring these under it, were compelled to feign some imaginary quantity whose square is -1; and then they acknowledged that, if quantities of the form a+b√-1 are conceded in the same way as real ones, the theorem is true not only for equations of the second degree, but also for cubics and biquadratics.
Hence indeed it was by no means permissible to infer that, with quantities of the form a+b√-1 admitted, any equation of the fifth or of higher degree can be satisfied; or—as it is for the most part expressed (although I should less approve the slippery phrase)—that the roots of any equation can be reduced to the form a+b√-1. This theorem differs in nothing from that which is enunciated in the title of this writing, if one looks to the matter itself; and to deliver a new rigorous demonstration of this constitutes the purpose of the present dissertation.
Ceterum ex eo tempore, quo analystae comperti sunt, infinite multas aequationes esse, quae nullam omnino radicem haberent, nisi quantitates formae a+b√-1 admittantur, tales quantitates fictiae tamquam peculiare quantitatum genus, quas imaginarias dixerunt, vt a realibus distinguerentur, consideratae et in totam analysin introductae sunt; quonam iure? hoc loco non disputo. — Demonstrationem meam absque omni quantitatum imaginarium subsidio absoluam, etsi eadem libertate, qua omnes recentiores analystae vsi sunt, etiam mihi vti liceret.
Moreover, from the time when the analysts discovered that there are infinitely many equations which would have no root at all unless quantities of the form a+b√-1 be admitted, such fictitious quantities, as a peculiar kind of quantities, which they called imaginary, so that they might be distinguished from the real, have been considered and introduced into the whole analysis; by what right? I do not dispute in this place. — I shall complete my demonstration without any support of imaginary quantities, although it would be permitted for me also to use the same liberty which all the more recent analysts have employed.
Quamuis ea, quae in plerisque libris elementaribus tamquam demonstratio theorematis nostri afferuntur, tam leuia sint, tantumque a rigore geometrico abhorreant, vt vix mentione sint digna tamen, ne quid deesse videatur, paucis illa attingam. ''Vt demonstrent, quamuis aequationem xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2 + etc. +M=0, siue X=0, reuera habere m radices, suscipiunt probare, X in m factores simplices resolui posse.
Although those things which in most elementary books are put forward as a demonstration of our theorem are so slight, and so far do they abhor geometric rigor, that they are scarcely worthy of mention, nevertheless, lest anything seem to be lacking, I shall touch on them briefly. ''In order to demonstrate that any equation xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2 + etc. +M=0, or X=0, actually has m roots, they undertake to prove that X can be resolved into m simple factors.
they say can be determined, since their multitude is also m. Namely that m-1 unknowns can be eliminated, whence there emerges an equation which contains only the single unknown that one may please. '' That I may be silent about the rest which could be reprehended in such an argumentation, I will merely ask: whence can we be certain that the last equation really has any root? Why could it not happen that neither this last equation nor the proposed one is satisfied by any magnitude in the whole ambit of real and imaginary quantities?
Quidam auctores, qui debilitatem huius methodi percepisse videntur, tamquam axioma assumunt, quamuis aequationem reuera habere radicos, si non possibiles, impossibiles. Quid sub quantitatibus possibilibus et impossibilibus intellegi velint, haud satis distincte exposuisse videntur. Si quantitates possibiles idem denotare debent vt reales, impossibiles idem vt imaginariae: axioma illud neutiquam admitti potest, sed necessario demonstratione opus habet.
Certain authors, who seem to have perceived the debility of this method, assume as an axiom that every equation truly has roots, if not possible, then impossible. What they wish to be understood under possible and impossible quantities they seem not to have explained with sufficient distinctness. If possible quantities are to denote the same as real ones, and impossible the same as imaginary ones, that axiom can by no means be admitted, but necessarily requires a demonstration.
However, the expressions do not seem to be to be taken in that sense, but the mind of the axiom seems rather to be this: "Although we are not yet certain that there necessarily are m real or imaginary quantities which satisfy a given equation of the mth degree, nevertheless we shall for a while suppose this; for if by chance it should happen that so many real and imaginary quantities cannot be found, surely a loophole will be open, namely to say that the remaining ones are impossible.'' If someone prefers to use this phrase rather than simply to say that in this case the equation will not have so many roots, nothing stands in the way on my part: but if then he uses these impossible roots as though they were something true, and, e.g., says that the sum of all the roots of the equation xm+Axm-1+ etc. =0 is =-A, even if impossible ones are among them (which expression properly signifies, even if some are lacking): this I can by no means approve.
For impossible roots, accepted in such a sense, are nevertheless roots, and then that axiom can in no way be admitted without demonstration, nor would you ineptly doubt whether equations could exist that have not even impossible roots? *1)
Antequam aliorum geometrarum demonstrationes theorematis nostri recenseam, et quae in singulis reprehenda mihi videantur, exponam: obseruo sufficere si tantummodo ostendatur, omni aequationi quantiuis gradus xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2+ etc. +M=0 siue X=0 (vbi coëfficientes A, B etc. reales esse supponuntur) ad minimum vno modo satisfieri posse per valorem ipsius x sub forma a+b√-1 contentum.
Before I review the demonstrations of our theorem by other geometers, and set forth what in each seems to me blameworthy, I observe: it suffices if it be shown only that every equation of whatever degree xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2+ etc. +M=0 or X=0 (where the coefficients A, B etc. are supposed to be real) can be satisfied at least in one way by a value of x contained under the form a+b√-1.
For it is evident that X will then be divisible by the real factor of the second degree xx-2ax+aa+bb, if b is not =0, and by the simple real factor x-a, if b=0. In either case the quotient will be real, and of a lower degree than X; and since this in the same way ought to have a real factor of the first or of the second degree, it is clear that, by the continuation of this operation, the function X will at length be resolved into real factors, simple or double; or, if for each real double factor you prefer to employ two simple imaginaries, into m simple factors.
Primo ostendit, si functio quaecunque X quantitatis variabilis x fiat =0 aut pro x=0 aut pro x=∞, atque valorem infinite paruum realem positiuum nancisci possit tribuendo ipsi x valorem realem: hanc functionem etiam valorem infinite paruum realem negatiuum obtinere posse per valorem ipsius x vel realem vel sub forma imaginaria p+q√-1 contentum. Scilicet designante Ω valorem infinite paruum ipsius X, et ω valorem respondentem ipsius x, asserit ω per seriem valde conuergentem aΩα+bΩβ+cΩγ etc. exprimi posse, vbi exponentes α, β, γ etc.
First he shows that, if any function X of the variable quantity
x becomes = 0 either for x = 0 or for x = ∞, and can obtain an infinitely
small positive real value by assigning to x a real value: then this function can also obtain an infinitely small
negative real value through a value of x either real or contained under the imaginary form p + q√-1.
Namely, letting Ω designate the infinitely small value of X, and ω the corresponding value
of x, he asserts that ω can be expressed by a very convergent series
aΩα + bΩβ + cΩγ etc., where the exponents are α, β, γ
etc.
let the exponents be rational quantities continuously increasing, and which at least, at a certain distance from the beginning, turn out positive, and render the terms in which they occur infinitely small. Now, if among all these exponents none occurs that is a fraction with an even denominator, all the terms of the series become real both for the positive and for the negative value of Ω; but if certain fractions with an even denominator are found among those exponents, it is established that, for the negative value of Ω, the corresponding terms are contained in the form p+q√-1. But on account of the infinite convergence of the series, in the former case it suffices if the first term (i.e., the maximum) alone is retained; in the latter, there is no need to proceed beyond that term which first produces the imaginary part.
Hinc sequitur, si X sit talis functio ipsius x, quae valorem realem V ex valore ipsius x reali v obtineat, atque etiam valorem realem quantitate infinite parua vel maiorem vel minorem ex valore reali ipsius x assequatur, eandem etiam valorem realem quantitate infinite parua atque adeo finite vel minorem vel maiorem quam V (resp.)recipere posse, tribuendo ipsi x valorem sub forma p+q√-1 contentum. Hoc nullo negotio ex praecc. deriuatur, si pro X substitui concipitur V+Y, et pro x, v+y.
Hence it follows, if X is such a function of x as obtains the real value V from the real value v of x, and also from a real value of x attains a real value greater or lesser by an infinitely small quantity, that the same function can also receive a real value greater or lesser by an infinitely small, and indeed by a finite, quantity than V (respectively)receive, by assigning to x a value contained under the form p+q√-1. This is derived with no trouble from the foregoing, if for X one conceives V+Y to be substituted, and for x, v+y.
Tandem affirmat ill. d'Alembert, si X totum interuallum aliquod inter duos valores reales R, S percurrere posse supponatur ( i. e. tum ipsi R, tum ipsi S, tum omnibus valoribus realibus intermediis aequalis fieri), tribuendo ipsi x valores semper in forma p+q√-1 contentos; functionem X quauis quantitate finita reali adhuc augeri vel diminui posse (prout S>R vel S<R), manente x semper sub forma p+q√-1. Si enim quantitas realis U daretur (inter quam et R supponitur S iacere), cui X per talem valorem ipsius x aequalis fieri non posset, necessario valorem maximum ipsius X dari (scilicet quando S>R; minimum vero, quando S<R), puta T, quem ex valore ipsius x, p+q√-1, consequeretur, ita vt ipsi x nullus valor sub simili forma contentus tribui posset, qui functionem X vel minimo excessu propius versus U promoueret. Iam si in aequatione inter X et x pro x vbique substituatur p+q√-1, atque tum pars realis, tum pars, quae factorem √-1 implicet, hoc omisso, cifrae aequentur: ex duabus aequationibus hinc prodeuntibus (in quibus p, q et X cum constantibus permixtae occurrent) per eliminationem duas alias elici posse, in quarum altera p, X et constantes reperiantur altera a p libera solas q, X et constantes inuoluat.
At length the illustrious d’Alembert affirms, if it be supposed that X can traverse some whole interval between two real values R, S (i. e. be made equal both to R and to S and to all the intermediate real values), by assigning to x values always contained in the form p+q√-1; that the function X can still be increased or diminished by any finite real quantity (as S>R or S<R), with x remaining always under the form p+q√-1. For if there were given a real quantity U (between which and R S is supposed to lie), to which X could not be made equal by such a value of x, then necessarily a maximum value of X would be given (namely when S>R; a minimum, truly, when S<R), to wit T, which it would attain from the value of x, p+q√-1, so that no value contained under a similar form could be assigned to x which would advance the function X toward U by even the least excess. Now if in the equation between X and x p+q√-1 be everywhere substituted for x, and then the real part and the part that involves the factor √-1, this being omitted, the coefficients be set equal: from the two equations hence proceeding (in which p, q and X occur commingled with constants) two others can be elicited by elimination, in one of which p, X and constants are found, the other, free from p, involves only q, X and constants.
Wherefore
when X, by the real values of p, q, has run through all the values from R up to T, by the foregoing X can still approach more closely to the value U by assigning to p, q such values α+γ√-1, β+δ√-1 respectively. Hence indeed it comes to be x=α-δ+(γ+β)√-1, i. e.
still to be under the form p+q√-1, contrary to the hypothesis.
Iam si X functionem talem vt xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2 + etc. +M denotare supponitur, nullo negotio perspicitur, ipsi x tales valores reales tribui posse, vt X totum aliquod interuallum inter duos valores reales percurrat. Quare x valorem aliquem sub forma p+q√-1 contentum talem etiam nancisci poterit, vnde X fiat =0. Q. E. D. *2)
Now if X is supposed to denote a function such as xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2 + etc. +M, it is seen without difficulty that such real values can be assigned to x that X traverses some entire interval between two real values. Wherefore x will also be able to obtain some value contained under the form p+q√-1, whence X becomes =0. Q. E. D. *2)
1. Ill. d'A. nullum dubium mouet de existentia valorum ipsius x quibus valores dati ipsius X respondeant, sed illam supponit, solamque formam istorum valorum inuestigat.
1. The illustrious d'A. raises no doubt about theexistence of the values of x
to which the given values of X correspond, but presupposes that, and investigates only the form of those values.
2. Assertio,ω per talem seriem qualem ponit semper exprimi posse, certo est falsa, si X etiam funcionem quamlibet transscendentem designare debet (vti d'A. pluribus locis innuit). Hoc e. g. manifestum est, si ponitur X=e1/x, siue x=1/log X. Attamen si demonstrationem ad eum casum restringimus, vbi X est functio algebraica ipsius x (quod in praesenti negotio sufficit), propositio vtique est vera. — Ceterum d'A. nihil pro confirmatione suppositionis suae attulit; cel. Bougainville supponit X esse functionem algebraicam ipsius x, et ad inuentionem seriei parallelogrammum Newtonianum commendat.
2. The assertion, thatω can always be expressed by such a series as he posits, is certainly false, if X is also to designate an arbitrary transcendental function (as d'A. hints in several places). This, e. g. is manifest, if one sets X=e1/x, or x=1/log X. However, if we restrict the demonstration to that case where X is an algebraic function of x (which in the present matter suffices), the proposition is indeed true. — Besides, d'A. brought forward nothing for the confirmation of his supposition; the celebrated Bougainville supposes X to be an algebraic function of x, and for the invention of the series recommends the Newtonian parallelogram.
3. Quantitatibus infinite paruis liberius vtitur, quam cum geometrico rigore consistere potest aut saltem nostra aetate (vbi illae merito male audiunt) ab analysta scrupuloso concederetur, neque etiam saltum a valore infinite paruo ipsiusΩ ad finitum satis luculenter explicauit. Propositionem suam, Ω etiam valorem aliquem finitum consequi posse, non tam ex possibilitate valoris infinite parui ipsius Ω, concludere videtur quam inde potius, quod denotante Ω quantitatem valde paruam, propter magnam seriei conuergentiam, quo plures termini seriei accipiantur, eo propius ad valorem verum ipsius ω accedatur, aut, quo plurium partium summa pro ω accipiatur, eo exactius aequtioni, quae relationem inter ω et Ω siue x et X exhibeat, satisfactum iri. Praeterea quod tota haec argumentatio nimis vaga videtur, quam vt ulla conclusio rigorosa inde colligi possit: obseruo, vtique dari series, quae quantumuis paruus valor quantitati, secundum cuius potestates progrediuntur, tribuatur, nihilominus semper diuergant, ita vt si modo satis longe continuentur, ad terminos quauis quantitate data maiores peruenire possis.
3. He employs infinitesimal quantities more freely than can consist with geometric rigor, or at least than in our age (when they deservedly have a bad reputation) would be conceded by a scrupulous analyst, nor has he explained with sufficient clarity the leap from an infinitely small value ofΩ to a finite one. His proposition, that Ω also can attain some finite value, seems to be concluded not so much from the possibility of an infinitely small value of Ω, as rather from this: that, Ω denoting a very small quantity, on account of the great convergence of the series, the more terms of the series are taken, the nearer one approaches to the true value of ω; or, the more the sum of several parts is taken for ω, the more exactly the equation which exhibits the relation between ω and Ω, or x and X, will be satisfied. Moreover, since all this argumentation seems too vague for any rigorous conclusion to be gathered from it, I observe that there indeed are series which, however small a value may be assigned to the quantity according to whose powers they proceed, nevertheless always diverge, so that, if only they be continued far enough, you can arrive at terms greater than any given quantity.
*3) This happens when the coëf-
ficients of the series constitute a hypergeometric progression. Wherefore it ought to have been necessarily demonstrated that such a hypergeometric series cannot arise in the present case.
4. Ex suppositione,X obtinere posse valorem S neque vero valorem U, nondum sequitur, inter S et U necessario valorem T iacere, quem X attingere sed non superare possit. Superest adhuc alius casus: scilicet fieri posset, vt inter S et U limes situs sit, ad quem accedere quidem quam prope velis possit X, ipsum vero nihilominus numquam attingere. Ex argumentis ab ill.
4. From the supposition, thatX can obtain the value S but not
the value U, it does not yet follow that between S and U there necessarily lies the value T
which X could attain but not surpass. There still remains
another case: namely, it could happen that between S and U a limit is
situated, to which X can indeed approach as near as you please, but
nevertheless never attain it. From the arguments by ill.
d'A.
from those adduced it only follows that X can still exceed by a finite quantity any value it has reached,
for instance when it has turned out = S, it can still be increased by some finite quantity Ω; this being done, a new
increment Ω′ is added, then again an augmentation Ω′′, etc., so that, however many increments have already been
added, none ought to be held as the last, but some new one can always be added. But although the multitude of
possible increments is circumscribed by no limits: nevertheless it could indeed happen that, if the increments
Ω, Ω′, Ω′′, etc. continually decreased, nonetheless the sum S+Ω+Ω′+Ω′′, etc.
Quamquam hic casus occurrere non potest, quando X designat functionem algebraicam integram ipsius x: tamen sine demonstratione, hoc fieri non posse, methodus necessario pro incompleta habenda est. Quando vero X est functio transscendens, siue etiam algebraica fracta, casus ille vtique locum habere potest, e. g. semper quando valori cuidam ipsius X valor infinite magnus ipsius x respondet. Tum methodus d'Alembertiana non sine multis ambagibus, et in quibusdam casibus nullo forsan modo, ad principia indubitata reduci posse videtur.
Although this case cannot occur, when X designates an entire algebraic function of x itself: nevertheless, without a demonstration that this cannot be done, the method must necessarily be held as incomplete. When indeed X is a transcendental function, or even a fractional algebraic one, that case indeed can have place, e. g. always whenever to some value of X there corresponds an infinitely great value of x. Then the d’Alembertian method seems, not without many circumlocutions, and in some cases perhaps in no way, to be reducible to indubitable principles.
Propter has rationes demonstrationem d'Alembertianam pro satisfaciente habere nequeo. Attamen hoc non obstante verus demonstrationis neruus probandi per omnes obiectiones neutiquam infringi mihi videtur, credoque eidem fundamento (quamuis longe diuersa ratione, et saltem maiori circumspicienta) non solum demonstrationem rigorosam theorematis nostri superstrui, sed ibinde omnia peti posse, quae circa aequationum transscendentium theoriam desiderari queant. De qua re grauissima alia occasione fusius agam; conf.
For these reasons I cannot hold the d'Alembertian demonstration as satisfactory. Nevertheless, this notwithstanding, the true nerve of the demonstration of proving seems to me by no means to be broken by all objections, and I believe that upon the same foundation (although by a far different method, and at least with greater circumspection) not only can a rigorous demonstration of our theorem be superstructured, but from there everything can be sought which might be desiderated concerning the theory of transcendental equations. On which most weighty matter I shall speak more fully on another occasion; conf.
are as yet unknown, and he sets their product equal to the function X. Then the comparison of coefficients supplies 2m-1 equations, and it need only be manifestly demonstrated that to the unknowns u, α, β etc., λ, μ etc. (whose multitude likewise is 2-1) real values of such a kind can be assigned as will satisfy those equations.
Now E. affirms that, if at the outset u be regarded as known, in such a way that the multitude of unknowns is less by one than the multitude of equations, then, these being duly combined according to the well-known algebraic methods, all α, β etc., λ, μ etc., can be obtained rationally and without any extraction of roots, by means of u and the coefficients B, C etc.
can be eliminated, so
that there comes forth the equation U=0, where U will be an integral function of u alone and of
the known coefficients. To work out this very equation by the common method
of elimination would be an immense labor,
when the proposed equation X=0 is of somewhat high degree; and
for an indeterminate degree, plainly impossible (in the judgment of E. himself, p. 239).
Nevertheless it suffices to have known one property of that equation,
namely that the last term in U (which does not involve the unknown u)
is necessarily negative, whence it is evident to follow that the equation
has at least one real root, namely u, and therefore also
α, β etc., λ, μ etc.
to be able at a minimum in one way to be determined in reality; and indeed one may confirm that property by the following reflections. Since xm-u xm-1+α xm-2+ etc. is supposed to be a factor of the function X: necessarily u will be the sum of m roots of the equation X=0, and so it must have just as many values as there are different ways in which out of 2m roots m can be selected, that is, by the principles of the calculus of combinations, (2m . 2m-1 . ... . m+1) / (1 . 2 . 3 ... m) values.
This number will always be oddly even (I suppress a not-difficult demonstration): if therefore it is set =2k, its half k will be odd; the equation U=0 indeed will be of degree 2kti. Now, since in the equation X=0 the second term is lacking, the sum of all the 2m roots will be 0; whence it is clear that, if the sum of any m roots is +p, the sum of the remaining will be -p, i. e. if +p is among the values of u, then -p will be among the same. Hence E. concludes that U is the product of k double factors such as uu-pp, uu-qq, vu-rr etc., denoting +p, -p, +q, -q etc., all the 2k roots of the equation U=0; whence, because of the odd multitude of these factors, the last term in U will be the square of the product pqr etc.
Quum hi duo factores reales ipsius X sint gradus mti atque m potestas numeri 2: eadem ratione vterque rursus in duos factores reales 1/2m dimensionum resolui poterit. Quoniam vero per repetitam dimidiationem numeri m necessario tandem ad binarium peruenitur, manifestum est, per continuationem operationis functionem X tandem in factores reales secundi gradus resolutam haberi.
Since these two real factors of X are of the mth degree, and m is a power of the number 2: by the same reasoning each in turn can be resolved into two real factors of 1/2m dimensions. But since by repeated halving of the number m one necessarily at length arrives at the number two, it is manifest that, by continuation of the operation, the function X is at length found resolved into real factors of the second degree.
Quodsi vero functio talis proponitur, in qua terminus secundus non deest, puta x2m+Ax2m-1+Bx2m-2+etc. +M, designante etiamnum 2m potestatem binariam, haec per substitutionem x=y-A/(2m) transibit in similem functionem termino secundo carentem. Vnde facile concluditur, etiam illam functionem in factores reales secundi gradus resolubilem esse.
But if indeed a function is proposed of such a sort in which the second term is not lacking, for instance x2m+Ax2m-1+Bx2m-2+etc. +M, with 2m still designating a binary power, this, by the substitution x=y-A/(2m), will pass into a similar function lacking the second term. Whence it is easily concluded that that function too is resolvable into real factors of the second degree.
Denique proposita functione gradus nti, designante n numerum, qui non est potestas binaria: ponatur potestas binaria proxime maior quam n, =2m, multiplicetur functio proposita per 2m-n factores simplices reales quoscunque. Ex resolubilitate producti in factores reales secundi gradus, nullo negotio deriuatur, etiam functionem propositam in factores reales secundi vel primi gradus resolubilem esse debere.
Finally, with a function of degree nth proposed, n designating a number
which is not a binary power: let the binary power next greater than n, =2m, be posited; let the proposed function be multiplied by
2m-n arbitrary simple real factors whatsoever. From the resolvability
of the product into real factors of the second degree, it is derived with no trouble
that the proposed function also must be resoluble into real factors of the second or
first degree.
1. Regulam, secundum quam E. concludit, ex2m-1 aequationibus 2m-2 incognitas α,β etc. λ, μ etc. omnes rationaliter determinari posse, neutiquam esse generalem, sed saepissime exceptionem pati.
1. The rule, according to which E. concludes that from2m-1 equations the 2m-2 unknowns α, β etc. λ, μ etc. can all be rationally determined, is by no means general, but very often admits an exception.
If someone, e. g. in art. 3, with other unknowns regarded as known, attempts to express the remaining ones rationally by means of this and the given coefficients, he will easily find that this is impossible, and that none of the unknown quantities can be determined otherwise than by an equation of the m-1th degree. Although indeed here one can at once perceive a priori that it must necessarily have turned out so; nevertheless one might rightly doubt whether also in the present case, for certain values of m itself, the matter stood in the same way; so that the unknowns α,β etc.
For that case where the equation X=0 is of the fourth degree, E. extracts the rational values of the coefficients by means of u and the given coefficients; but that the same also can be done in all higher equations certainly required a fuller explication. — Moreover, it seems worth the work, to go into those formulas which express α, β etc. rationally through u, B, C etc.
2. Etiamsi autem demonstratum fuerit, cuiusuis gradus sit aequatioX=0, semper formulas inueniri posse, quae ipsas α, β etc. λ, μ etc. rationaliter per u, B, C etc.
2. Even if, however, it should be demonstrated, of whatever degree the equationX=0 may be, that formulas can always be found which express the very α, β etc., λ, μ etc., rationally through u, B, C etc.
they may exhibit: nevertheless
it is certain that, for certain determinate values of the coefficients
B, C etc., those formulas can turn out indeterminate, so that not
only is it impossible to define those unknowns rationally from u, B, C
etc., but indeed, in some cases, to some real value of the
u itself there correspond no real values of α, β etc.
that same E., where on p. 236 the equation of the fourth degree is more fully explained. At once anyone will see that the formulas for the coefficients α, β become indeterminate if C=0 and the value 0 is assumed for u, and that their values not only cannot be assigned without extraction of roots, but indeed are not even real, if BB-4D is a negative quantity.
Although indeed in this case u can still have other real values, to which real values of α, β correspond, this can easily be perceived: nevertheless someone might fear, lest the resolution of this difficulty (which E. did not touch at all) in higher equations would occasion much greater labor. Certainly this matter ought by no means to be passed over in silence in an exact demonstration.
3. Ill. E. supponit tacite, aequationemX=0 habere 2m radices, harumque summam statuit =0 ideo quod terminus secundus in X abest. Quomodo de hac licentia (qua omnes auctores de hoc argumento vtuntur) sentiam, iam supra art.
3. The Ill. E. supposes tacitly that the equationX=0 has 2m roots, and he posits their sum =0 for the reason that the second term in X is absent. How I judge about this license (which all authors on this argument use), already above art.
3. I have declared. The proposition, that the sum of all the roots of some equation is equal to the first coefficient, with the sign changed, does not seem applicable to other equations, except those which have roots: now, since by this very demonstration it ought to be proved that the equationX=0 really has roots, it does not seem permitted to assume their existence. Without doubt those who have not yet penetrated the fallacy of this paralogism will reply that what is not being demonstrated here is that the equation X=0 can be satisfied (for this is what the expression means, that it has roots), but only that it can itself be satisfied by the values of x contained under the form a+b√-1; whereas that is being assumed as an axiom.
But since other forms of quantities, besides the real and the imaginary a+b√-1, cannot be conceived, it does not seem sufficiently lucid how that which must be demonstrated differs from that which is assumed as an axiom; indeed, even if it were possible still to devise other forms of quantities, for example the form F, F′, F′′ etc., nevertheless it ought not to be admitted without demonstration that there is an equation for which it is possible to be satisfied by some value of x either real, or contained under the form a+b√-1, or under the form F, or under F′ etc.
Wherefore that axiom can have no other sense than this: An equation can be satisfied either by a real value of the unknown, or by an imaginary value contained under the form a+b√-1, or perhaps by a value contained under some other form hitherto unknown, or by a value that is contained under no form at all. But how quantities of this sort — of which you cannot even fashion an idea, a true shadow of a shadow — could be summed or multiplied; this, with that perspicuity which is always demanded in mathematics, is certainly not understood.*4)
Ceterum conclusiones, quas E. ex suppositione sua elicuit, per has obiectiones haudquaquam suspectas reddere volo; quin potius certus sum, illas per methodum neque difficilem neque ab Euleriana multum diuersam ita comprobari posse, vt nemini vel minimus scrupulus superesse debeat. Solam formam reprehendo, quae quamuis in inueniendis nouis veritatibus magnae vtilitatis esse possit, tamen in demonstrando, coram publico, minime probanda videtur.
Moreover, the conclusions which E. elicited from his supposition,
I by no means wish to render suspect by these objections; rather
I am certain that they can be confirmed by a method neither difficult nor
much different from the Eulerian, so that not even the least scruple
ought to remain to anyone. I censure only the form,
which, although in finding new truths it can be of great utility,
yet in demonstrating, before the public, seems by no means
to be approved.
4. Pro demonstratione assertionis, productumpqr etc. ex coëfficientibus in X rationaliter determinari posse, ill. E. nihil omnino attulit.
4. For a demonstration of the assertion that the productpqr etc., from the coefficients in X, can be determined rationally, the illustrious E. adduced nothing at all.
''On m'objectera sans doute, que j'al supposé ici, que la quantité pqr étoit une quantité réelle, et que son quarré ppqqrr étoit affirmatif; ce qui étoit encor douteux, vu que les racines a, b, c, d étant imaginaire, il pourroit bien arriver, que le quarré de la quantité pqr, qui en es composée, fut negatif. Or je reponds à cela que ce cas ne sauroit jamais avoir lieu; car quelque imaginaires que soient les racines a,b,c,d, on sait pourtant, qu'il doit y avoir a+b+c+d=0; ab+ac+ad+bc +bb+cd=B; abc+abd+acd+bcd=-C *5); abcd =D, ces quantités B,C,D étant réelles. Mais puisque p= a+b, q=a+c, r=a+b, leur produit pqr=(a+b)(a+c)a+d) est determinable comme on sait, par les quantités B,C,D, et sera par conseéquent réel, tout comme nous avons vu, qu'il est effectivement pqr=-C, et ppqqrr=CC. On reconnoitra aisément de même, que dans les plus hautes équations cette même circonstance doit avoir lieu, et qu'on ne sauroit me faire des objections de ce coté.'' Conditionem, productum pqr etc.
''One will no doubt object to me that I have supposed here that the quantity pqr was a real quantity, and that its square ppqqrr was affirmative; which was still doubtful, since the roots a, b, c, d being imaginary, it might well happen that the square of the quantity pqr, which is composed from them, was negative. Now I reply to this that this case can never take place; for however imaginary the roots a, b, c, d, may be, one nevertheless knows that there must be a+b+c+d=0; ab+ac+ad+bc +bb+cd=B; abc+abd+acd+bcd=-C *5); abcd =D, these quantities B, C, D being real. But since p= a+b, q=a+c, r=a+b, their product pqr=(a+b)(a+c)a+d) is determinable, as is known, by the quantities B, C, D, and will consequently be real, just as we have seen that in fact pqr=-C, and ppqqrr=CC. One will easily recognize likewise that in the higher equations this same circumstance must obtain, and that one cannot make objections to me on this side.'' The condition, the product pqr etc.
rationally to be able to be determined through B, C, etc., E. added nowhere; nevertheless he seems always to have tacitly understood it, since without that the demonstration can have no force. Now it is indeed true in equations of the fourth degree, if the product (a+b)(a+c)(a+d) is expanded, that one obtains aa(a+b+c+d)+abc+abd+acd+bcd=-C; nevertheless it does not seem sufficiently perspicuous how in all higher equations the product can be determined rationally through the coëfficients.
T. 1. p. 117.), rightly contends that, without a rigorous demonstration of this proposition, the method loses all force; he confesses, moreover, that that seems to him rather difficult, and he relates which path he tried in vain. *6) Nevertheless, this matter is disposed of without much difficulty by the following method (the sum of which I can only append here): Although in equations of the fourth degree it is not sufficiently clear that the product (a+b)(a+c)(a+d) is determinable through the coefficients B, C, D, yet it is easy to perceive that the same product is also = (b+a)(b+c)(b+d), and likewise =(c+a)(c+b)(c+d), and finally also =(d+a)(d+b)(d+c). Wherefore the product pqr will be a quarter of the sum (a+b)(a+c)(a+d)+(b+a)(b+c)(b+d)+ (c+a)(c+b)(c+d)+(b+a)(b+d)(d+c), which, if it be expanded, will be a rational entire function of the roots a, b, c, d, such that all enter in the same manner—something that can be foreseen a priori without any trouble. Such functions, moreover, can always be expressed rationally through the coefficients of the equation whose roots are a, b, c, d.
quod productum euolutum omnes a, b, c, d eodem modo implicaturum esse facile praeuideri potest. Simul periti facile hinc colligent, quomodo hoc ad altiores aequationes applicare debeat. — Completam demonstrationis expositionem, quam hic apponere breuitas non permittit, vna cum vberiori disquisitione de functionibus plures variabiles eodem modo inuoluentibus ad aliam occasionem mihi reseruo.
that the expanded product will easily be foreseen to involve all a, b, c, d in the same way. At the same time the skilled will easily gather from this how one ought to apply this to higher equations. — A complete exposition of the demonstration, which brevity does not permit to append here, together with a more copious disquisition concerning functions involving several variables in the same way, I reserve for another occasion.
Ceterum obseruo, praeter has quatuor obiectiones, adhuc quaedam alia in demonstratione E. reprehendi posse, quae tamen silentio praetereo, ne forte censor nimis seuerus esse videar, praesertim quum praecedentia satis ostendere videatur, demonstrationem in ea quidem forma, in qua ab E. proposita est, pro completa neutiquam haberi posse.
Moreover I observe, besides these four objections, still
that certain other things in E.’s demonstration can be reprehended, which, however,
I pass over in silence, lest perhaps I should seem a too severe censor,
especially since what precedes seems sufficiently to show that the demonstration,
in the very form in which it has been proposed by E., can by no means be
held as complete.
Post hanc demonstrationem, E. adhuc aliam viam theorema pro aequationibus, quarum gradus non est potestas binaria, ad talium aequationum resolutionem reducendi ostendit: attamen quum methodus haec pro aequationibus quarum gradus est potestas binaria, nihil doceat, insuperque omnibus obiectionibus praecc. (praeter quartam) aeque obnoxia sit vt demonstratio prima generalis: haud necesse est illam hic fusius explicare.
After this demonstration, E. further showed another way of reducing the theorem for equations whose degree is not a binary power to the resolution of such equations: however, since this method, for equations whose degree is a binary power, teaches nothing, and moreover is equally liable to all the preceding objections (except the fourth) as the first general demonstration, it is by no means necessary to explain it here more fully.
In eadem commentatione ill. E. theorema nostrum adhuc alia via confirmare annixus est p. 263, cuius summa continetur in his: Proposita aequatione xn+Axn-1+Bxn-2 etc. =0, hucusque quidem expressio analytica, quae ipsius radices exprimat, inueniri non potuit, si exponens n>4; attamen certum esse videtur (vti asserit E.), illam nihil aliud continere posse, quam operationes arithmeticas et extractiones radicum eo magis complicatas, quo maior sit n. Si hoc conceditur, E. optime ostendit, quantumuis inter se complicata sint signa radicalia, tamen formulae valorem semper per formam M+N√-1 repraesentabilem fore, ita vt M, N sint quantitates reales.
In the same commentary the ill. E. has endeavored still by another way to confirm our theorem on p. 263, the sum of which is contained in these points: the equation xn+Axn-1+Bxn-2 etc. =0 being proposed, up to this point indeed an analytic expression that would express its roots has not been able to be found, if the exponent n>4; yet it seems certain (as E. asserts) that it can contain nothing else than arithmetical operations and extractions of roots, the more complicated the greater n is. If this is conceded, E. shows very well that, however complicated the radical signs may be among themselves, nevertheless the value of the formula will always be representable by the form M+N√-1, so that M, N are real quantities.
Contra hoc ratiocinium obiici potest, post tot tantorum geometrarum labores perexiguam spem superesse, ad resolutionem generalem aequationum algebraicarum vmquam perueniendi, ita vt magis magisque verisimile fiat, talem resolutionem omnino esse impossibilem et contradictoriam. Hoc eo minus paradoxum videri debet, quum id quod vulgo resolutio aequationis dicitur proprie nihil aliud sit quam ipsius reductio ad aequationes puras. Nam aequationum purarum solutio hinc non docetur sed supponitur, et si radicem aequationis xm=H per m√H exprimis illam neutiquam soluisti, neque plus fecisti, quam si ad denotandam radicem aequationis xn+Axn-1+ etc.
Against this reasoning it can be objected that, after so many labors of so many geometers, a very slight hope remains of ever attaining to the general resolution of algebraic equations, so that it becomes more and more likely that such a resolution is altogether impossible and contradictory. This ought to seem the less paradoxical, since that which is commonly called the resolution of an equation is properly nothing else than its reduction to pure equations. For the solution of pure equations is here not taught but presupposed, and if you express the root of the equation xm=H by m√H you have by no means solved it, nor have you done more than if, for denoting the root of the equation xn+Axn-1+ etc.
=0 you might devise some sign, and set the root equal to this. It is true that pure equations,
on account of the facility of finding their roots by approximation,
and because of the elegant nexus which all the roots have among
themselves, excel greatly above all the rest; and so it is by no means to be blamed
that analysts have denoted the roots of these by a peculiar sign: nevertheless, from the fact that this sign,
just like the arithmetic signs of addition, subtraction, multiplication,
division, and elevation to a power, has been embraced into dignity under the name analytical
expressions, it by no means follows that one can exhibit the root of any equation by them. Or, in short, it is
assumed without sufficient reason that the solution of any equation can be reduced to the solution
of pure equations.
Perhaps it would not be so difficult to demonstrate, already with full rigor, the impossibility for the fifth degree, on which matter elsewhere I shall more fully propose my disquisitions. Here it suffices that the general resolvability of equations, taken in that sense, is still very doubtful, and thus the demonstration whose whole force depends on that supposition, in the present state of the matter, has no weight.
Proposita sit aequatio Z=0, designante Z functionem mti gradus incognitae z. Si m est numerus impar, iam constat, aequationem hanc habere radicem realem; si vero m est par, clar. F. sequenti modo probare conatur, aequationem ad minimum vnam radicem formae p+q√-1 habere. Sit m=2ni, designante i numerum imparem, supponaturque zz+uz+M esse diuisor functionis Z. Tunc singuli valores ipsius u erunt summae binarum radicum aequationis Z=0 (mutato signo), quamobrem u habebit (m . m-t) / (1 . 2)=m′ valores, et si u per aequationem U=0 determinari supponitur (designante U functionem integram ipsius u et coëfficientium cognitorum in Z), haec erit gradus m′ti. Facile vero perspicitur m′ fore numerum formae 2n-1i′, designante i′ numerum imparem.
Let the equation Z=0 be proposed, with Z designating a function of the mti degree of the unknown z. If m is an odd number, it is already established that this equation has a real root; but if m is even, the renowned F. tries to prove in the following way that the equation has at least one root of the form p+q√-1. Let m=2ni, with i denoting an odd number, and let it be supposed that zz+uz+M is a divisor of the function Z. Then the individual values of u will be the sums of pairs of roots of the equation Z=0 (with the sign changed), wherefore u will have (m . m-t) / (1 . 2)=m′ values; and if u is supposed to be determined by the equation U=0 (with U designating an integral function of u itself and of the coefficients known in Z), this will be of the m′ti degree. It is, indeed, easily seen that m′ will be a number of the form 2n-1i′, with i′ denoting an odd number.
Now unless m′ is odd, let it again be supposed that uu+uu′+M′ is a divisor of U itself, and it is clear by similar reasonings that u′ is determined by the equation U′=0, where U′ is a function of the (m′ . m′-1) / (1 . 2)th degree of u′. And if one sets (m′ . m′-1) / (1 . 2)=m′′, then m′′ will be a number of the form 2n-2i′′, with i′′ denoting an odd number. Now unless m′′ is odd, let it be established that u′ u′+u′′u′+M′′ is a divisor of the function U′, and then u′′ will be determined by the equation U′′=0, which, if it is supposed to be of the m′′′th degree, m′′′ will be a number of the form sn-3i′′′. It is manifest that, in the series of equations U=0, U′=0, U′′=0, etc., the nth will be of odd degree and so will have a real root.
We will set, for brevity’s sake, n=3, so that the equation U′′=0 has a real root u′′; for with no trouble it is evident that for any other value of n the same ratiocination holds. Then the celebrated de F. asserts that the coefficient M′′ is rationally determinable through u′′ and the coefficients in U′ (which are easily understood to be integral functions of the coefficients in Z), or through u′′ and the coefficients in Z, and therefore real.
Hence it follows that the roots of the equation u′ u′+u′′u′+M′′=0 will be contained under the form p+q√-1; and these same will plainly
satisfy the equation U′=0: wherefore some value of u′ will be given, contained under the form p+q√-1. Now the coefficient M′ (in the same
way as above) can be determined rationally through u′ and the coefficients in Z, and thus will likewise be contained under the form p+q√-1;
wherefore the roots of the equation uu+u′ u+M′ will be contained under the same form, and at the same time will satisfy the equation U=0, i. e. the equation
will have a root contained under the form p+q√-1. Finally,
hence by a like reasoning it follows that M also is contained under the same form, and likewise the root of the equation zz+uz+M=0, which
will plainly also satisfy the proposed equation Z=0.
Obiectiones 1, 2, 3, quas contra Euleri demonstrationem primam feci (art. 8.), eandem vim contra hanc methodum habent, ea tamen differentia, vt obiectio secunda, cui Euleri demonstratio tantummodo in quibusdam casibus specialibus obnoxia erat, praesentem in omnibus casibus attingere debeat. Scilicet a priori demonstrari potest, etiamsi formula detur, quae coëfficientem M′ rationaliter per u′ et coëfficientes in Z exprimat, hanc pro pluribus valoribus ipsius u′ necessario indeterminatam fieri debere; similiterque formulam, quae coëfficientem M′′ per u′′ exhibeat, indeterminatam fieri pro quibusdam valoribus ipsius u′′ etc.
Objections 1, 2, 3, which I made against Euler’s first demonstration (art. 8.), have the same force against this method,
with this difference, however, that the second objection, to which Euler’s demonstration
was liable only in certain special cases,
ought to apply to the present method in all cases. Namely, it can be demonstrated a priori
that, even if a formula is given which expresses the coefficient M′
rationally in terms of u′ and the coefficients in Z, this must necessarily become indeterminate for several
values of u′ itself; and similarly that the formula which exhibits the coefficient M′′ by means of u′′
becomes indeterminate for certain values of u′′ itself, etc.
This will be seen most lucidly, if we assume for an example an equation of the fourth degree. Let us therefore set m=4, and let the roots of the equation Z=0 be these α, β, γ, δ. Then it is clear that the equation U=0 will be of the sixth degree and will have as its roots -(α+β), -(α+γ), -(α+δ), -(β+γ), -(β+δ), -(γ+δ). But the equation U′=0 will be of the fifteenth degree, and the values of u′ are these 2α+β+γ, 2α+β+δ, 2α+γ+δ, 2β+α+γ, 2β+α+δ, 2β+γ+δ, 2γ+α+β, 2γ+α+δ, 2γ+β+δ, 2δ+α+β, 2δ+α+γ, 2δ+β+γ, α+β+γ+δ, α+β+γ+δ, α+β+γ+δ. Now in this equation, since its degree is odd, one must stop, and in fact it will truly have the real root α+β+γ+δ (which, with the first coefficient in Z having its sign changed, is equal thereto, and thus not only real but also rational, if the coefficients in Z are rational). But it can be seen without any trouble that, if a formula is given which exhibits the value of M′ rationally by the corresponding value of u′, this must necessarily become indeterminate for u′=α+β+γ+δ. For this value will be a root of the equation U′=0 ter, and there will correspond to it three values of M′, namely (α+β)(γ+δ), (α+γ)(β+δ) and (α+δ)(β+γ), which can all be irrational.
Manifestly, however, a rational formula could in this case produce neither an irrational value of M′, nor three distinct values. From this specimen it can be sufficiently gathered that the method of the illustrious de Foncenex is by no means satisfactory, but that, if it is to be rendered complete in every respect, one must inquire much more profoundly into the theory of elimination.
p. 222 sqq. This great geometer in the first place devoted his efforts to supplement the defects in Euler’s first demonstration, and indeed he investigated especially those things which above (art. 8) constitute the third and fourth objection so profoundly that nothing further remains to be desired, unless perhaps in the prior disquisition on the theory of elimination (on which this whole investigation rests) certain doubts seem to remain.
Demonstr. Pro m=1 functio illa sit =0 adeoque per quemcunque factorem diuisibilis; pro m=2 quotiens sit sin φ, et pro quouis valore maiori quotiens erit sin φ. xm-2+sin 2φ. rxm-3 +sin3φ. rrxm-4+ etc. +sin(m-1)φ. rm-2. Facile enim confirmatur multiplicata hac functione per xx-2cosφ. rx+rr, productum functioni propositae aequale fieri.
Demonstr. For m=1 let that function be =0 and so divisible by any factor; for m=2 let the quotient be sin φ, and for any greater value the quotient will be sin φ. xm-2+sin 2φ. rxm-3 +sin3φ. rrxm-4+ etc. +sin(m-1)φ. rm-2. For it is easily confirmed that, this function having been multiplied by xx-2cosφ. rx+rr, the product becomes equal to the proposed function.
[1]
rm sin mφ+Arm-1 sin(m-1)φ+Brm-2 sin(m-2)φ+ etc.
+Krrsin2φ+Lrsinφ=0
[1]
rm sin mφ+Arm-1 sin(m-1)φ+Brm-2 sin(m-2)φ+ etc.
+Krrsin2φ+Lrsinφ=0
[2]
functio xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2+ etc. +Kxx+Lx+M=X
diuisibilis erit per factorem duplicem xx-2cosφ. rx+rr, si modo
r. sinφ non =0; si vero r. sinφ=0, eadem functio diuisibilis erit
per factorem simplicem x-rcosφ.
[2]
the function xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2+ etc. +Kxx+Lx+M=X
will be divisible by the double factor xx-2cosφ. rx+rr, provided that
r. sinφ is not =0; if, however, r. sinφ=0, the same function will be divisible
by the simple factor x-rcosφ.
[2]; tertiarum vero aggregatum quoque euanescere, facile perspicitur, si
[2]; moreover, that the aggregate of the third parts likewise disappears is easily perceived, if
[2] percosφ, productumque illud ab hoc subducitur. Vnde sequitur, functionem sinφ. rX diuisibilem esse per xx-2cosφ. rx+rr, adeoque, nisi fuerit rsinφ=0, etiam functionem X. Q. E. P.
[2] bycosφ, and that product is subtracted from this. Whence it follows that the function sinφ. rX is divisible by xx-2cosφ. rx+rr, and hence, unless rsinφ=0, the function X as well. Which was to be proved.
II. Si verorsinφ=0, erit aut r=0 aut sinφ=0. In casu priori erit M=0, propter
2. But ifrsinφ=0, there will be either r=0 or sinφ=0. In the former case there will be M=0, because
[1], adeoqueX per x siue per x-rcosφ diuisibilis; in posteriori erit cosφ=±1, cos2φ= +1, cos3φ=±1 et generaliter cos nφ=cosφn. Quare propter
[1], and thusX is divisible by x or by x-rcosφ; in the latter case there will be cosφ=±1, cos2φ= +1, cos3φ=±1 and in general cos nφ=cosφn. Wherefore, on account of
[1] fietX=0, statuendo x=cosφ, et proin functio X per x-cosφ erit diuisibilis. Q. E. S.
[1] it will beX=0, by setting x=cosφ, and hence the function X by
x-cosφ will be divisible. Q. E. S.
Inf. T. I.
p. 110; I judged it worth the effort to show how just as easily it can be derived without the aid of those. It is now manifest that for the demonstration of our theorem nothing else is required than that it be shown: Given any function X of the form xm+Axm-1+Bxm-2+ etc.+Lx+M, r and φ can be so determined, that the equations
[2]locum habeant. Hinc enim sequetur, X habere factorem realem primi vel secundi gradus; diuisio autem necessario producet quotientem realem inferioris gradus, qui ex eadem ratione quoque factorem primi vel secundi gradus habebit. Per continuationem huius operationis X tandem in factores reales simplices vel duplices resoluetur. Illud itaque theorema demonstrare, propositum est sequentium disquisitionum.
[2]hold good. Hence indeed it will follow that X has a real factor of the first or second degree; but division will necessarily produce a real quotient of lower degree, which for the same reason will also have a factor of the first or second degree. By the continuation of this operation X will at length be resolved into real factors, simple or double. To demonstrate that theorem, therefore, is the aim of the following disquisitions.
Concipiatur planum fixum infinitum (planum tabulae, fig. 1.), et in hoc recta fixa infinita GC per punctum fixum C transiens. Assumta aliqua longitudine pro vnitate vt omnes rectae per numeros exprimi possint, erigatur in quouis puncto plani P, cuius distantia a centro C est r angulusque GCP=φ, perpendiculum aequale valori expressionis rmsin mφ+Arm-1sin(m-1)φ+ etc.+Lrsinφ, quem breuitatis gratia in sequentibus semper per T designabo.
Let a fixed infinite plane be conceived (the plane of the board, fig. 1.), and in it a fixed infinite straight line GC passing through the fixed point C. Some length having been assumed for the unit so that all straight lines can be expressed by numbers, let there be erected at any point of the plane P, whose distance
from the center C is r and whose angle GCP=φ, a perpendicular
equal to the value of the expression rmsin mφ+Arm-1sin(m-1)φ+
etc.+Lrsinφ, which for the sake of brevity I shall always designate in what follows by T.
I always consider the distance r as positive, and for the points which lie on the other side of the axis, the angle φ must be regarded either as greater than two right angles, or as negative (which here comes to the same thing). The extremities of these perpendiculars (which, for a positive value of T, are to be taken above the plane, for a negative below, for a vanishing one in the plane itself) will be on a continuous curved surface, infinite in all directions, which for brevity in what follows I shall call the first surface. In entirely similar manner, with reference to the same plane and center and the same axis, let another surface be referred, whose height above any point of the plane is rmcos mφ+Arm-1cos(m-1)φ+ etc.
+Lrcosφ+M, which expression for brevity I will always denote by U. This surface, moreover, which also will be continuous and in every direction infinite, I shall distinguish from the former by the denomination of the second surface. Then it is manifest that the whole business turns on this: that it be demonstrated that at least one point is given which at the same time lies in the plane, in the first surface, and in the second surface.
Facile perspici potest, superficiem primam partim supra planum partim infra planum iacere; patet enim distantiam a centro r tam magnam accipi posse, vt reliqui termini in T prae primo rmsin mφ euanescant; hic vero, angulo φ rite determinato, tam positiuus quam negatiuus fieri potest. Quare planum fixum necessario a superficie prima secabitur; hanc plani cum superficie prima intersectionem vocabo lineam primam; quae itaque determinabitur per aequationem T=0. Ex eadem ratione planum a superficie secunda secabitur; intersectio constituet curuam per aequationem U=0 determinatam, quam lineam secundam appellabo. Proprie vtraque curua ex pluribus ramis constabit, qui omnino seiuncti esse possunt, singuli vero erunt lineae continuae.
It can easily be perceived that the first surface lies partly above the plane partly below the plane; for it is evident that the distance from the center r can be taken so great that the remaining terms in T, in comparison with the first rmsin mφ, vanish; but this, the angle φ being properly determined, can be made both positive and negative. Wherefore the fixed plane will necessarily be cut by the first surface; this intersection of the plane with the first surface I shall call the first line; which therefore will be determined by the equation T=0. By the same reasoning the plane will be cut by the second surface; the intersection will constitute a curve determined by the equation U=0, which I shall call the second line. Properly, each curve will consist of several branches, which can be altogether disjoined, but each will be a continuous line.
Nay even, the first line will always be of such a sort as they call a complex, and the axis GC is to be regarded as a part of this curve; for whatever value is assigned to r, U will always become =0 when φ is either =0 or =180°. But it is better to consider as one curve the complex of all the branches passing through all the points where T=0 (according to the usage generally received in higher geometry), and similarly all the branches passing through all the points where U=0. It is now clear that the matter has been reduced to this: that it be demonstrated that there exists in the plane at least one point where some branch of the first line is cut by a branch of the second line. To this end, it will be necessary to contemplate more closely the character of these lines.
Ante omnia obseruo, vtramque curuam esse algebraicam, et quidem, si ad coordinates orthogonales reuocetur, ordinis mti. Sumto enim initio abscissarum in C, abscissisque x versus G, applicatis y versus P, erit x=rcosφ, y=rsinφ, adeoque generaliter, quidquid sit n, rnsin nφ=nxn-1y-(n. n-1. n-2) / (1. 2. 3) xn-3y3 +(n. .. n-4) / (1. .. .5) xn-5y5- etc., rncos nφ=xn-(n. n-1) / (1. 2) xn-2yy +(n. n-1. n-2. n-3) / (1. 2. 3. 4) xn-4y4- etc. Quamobrem tum T tum U constabunt ex pluribus huiusmodi terminis axα yβ, denotantibus α, β numeros integros positiuos, quorum summa, vbi maxima est, sit =m. Ceterum facile praeuideri potest, cunctos terminos ipsius T factorem y inuoluere, adeoque lineam primam proprie ex recta (cuius aequatio y=0) et curua ordinis m-1ti compositam esse; sed necesse non est ad hanc distinctionem hic respicere.
Before all things I observe that each curve is algebraic, and indeed, if it be referred to orthogonal coordinates, of order mth. For, with the origin of abscissas taken at C, the abscissas x directed toward G, the ordinates y toward P, it will be x=rcosφ, y=rsinφ, and thus in general, whatever n may be, rnsin nφ=nxn-1y-(n. n-1. n-2) / (1. 2. 3) xn-3y3 +(n. .. n-4) / (1. .. .5) xn-5y5- etc., rncos nφ=xn-(n. n-1) / (1. 2) xn-2yy +(n. n-1. n-2. n-3) / (1. 2. 3. 4) xn-4y4- etc. Wherefore both T and U will consist of several terms of this kind axα yβ, α, β denoting positive integers, whose sum, where it is maximal, is =m. Moreover, it can easily be foreseen that all the terms of T involve the factor y, and so the first line is properly composed of a straight line (whose equation is y=0) and of a curve of order m-1th; but it is not necessary here to have regard to this distinction.
Maioris momenti erit inuestigatio, an linea prima et secunda crura infinita habeant, et quot qualiaque. In distantia infinita a puncto C linea prima, cuius aequatio sin mφ+1/r sin(m-1)φ +B/rr sin(m-2)φ etc. =0, confundetur cum linea, cuius aequatio sin mφ=0. Haec vero exhibet m lineas rectas in puncto A se secantes, quarum prima est axis GCG′, reliquae contra hanc sub angulis 1/m 180, 2/m 180, 3/m 180 etc.
Of greater moment will be the investigation, whether the first and second line have infinite branches, and how many and of what sort. At infinite distance from the point C the first line, whose equation is sin mφ+1/r sin(m-1)φ +B/rr sin(m-2)φ etc. =0, will be confounded with the line whose equation is sin mφ=0. This indeed exhibits m straight lines intersecting one another at the point A, of which the first is the axis GCG′, the remaining against this under angles 1/m 180, 2/m 180, 3/m 180 etc.
inclined by degrees. Wherefore the first line has 2m infinite branches, which are distributed over the periphery of a circle described with infinite radius into 2m equal parts, so that the periphery is cut by the first branch at the concurrence of the circle and the axis, by the second at a distance 1/m 180°, by the third at a distance 2/m 180°, etc. In the same way the second line, at infinite distance from the center, will have an asymptote expressed by the equation cos mφ=0, which is a complex of m straight lines intersecting one another at equal angles at point C, yet in such a way that the first with the axis CG forms an angle 1/m 90°, the second an angle 3/m 90°, the third an angle 5/m 90°, etc.
Therefore the second line will likewise have 2m infinite branches, each of which will occupy the middle place between the two nearest branches of the first line, so that they cut the periphery of the circle described with an infinitely great radius at the points which are distant from the axis by 1/m 90°, 3/m 90°, 5/m 90°, etc. Moreover, it is plain that the axis itself always constitutes two infinite branches of the first line, to wit the first and the m+1th. Most lucidly the disposition of the branches is exhibited here in the fig.
2, constructed for the case m=4, where the branches of the second line, so that they may be distinguished from the branches of the first line, are expressed as dotted, which likewise is to be held for the fourth figure. *8) — Since indeed these conclusions are of the greatest moment, and infinitely great quantities may offend some readers: these also, without the assistance of infinities, will be set forth in the following article.
Sit summa omnium coëfficientium A,B etc. K,L,M, positiue acceptorum =S, accipiaturque R simul >S√2 et >1 *9): tum dico in circulo radio R descripto ea, quae in theoremate enunciata sunt, necessario locum habere. Scilicet designato breuitatis gratia eo puncto huius circumferentiae, quod 1/m 45 gradibus ab ipsius concursu cum laeua parte axis distat, siue pro quo φ= 1/m 45°, per (1); similiter eo puncto, quod φ=3/m 45°, ab hoc concursu distat, siue pro quo φ=3/m 45°, per (3); porro eo, vbi φ=5/m 45°, per (5) etc.
Let the sum of all the coefficients A, B etc. K, L, M, taken as positive, be = S, and let R at the same time be taken > S√2 and > 1 *9): then I say that in the circle described with radius R those things that were stated in the theorem necessarily hold. Namely, for brevity’s sake, having designated that point of this circumference which is distant by 1/m 45 degrees from its intersection with the left-hand part of the axis, that is, for which φ= 1/m 45°, by (1); similarly that point which, being φ=3/m 45°, is distant from this intersection, that is, for which φ=3/m 45°, by (3); further, that where φ=5/m 45°, by (5) etc.
up to (8m-1), which is distant by (8m-1)/m 45 degrees from that concurrence, if you always advance toward the same side (or by 1/m 45° from the opposite side), so that in all 4m points are had on the periphery, separated by equal intervals: there will lie between (8m-1) and (1) one point, for which T=0; and likewise similar single points will be situated between (3) and (5); between (7) and (9); between (11) and (13), etc., whose multitude therefore is 2m; and in the same way single points, for which U=0, will lie between (1) and (3); between (5) and (7); between (9) and (11), whose multitude therefore likewise =2m; finally, besides these 4m points, there will not be given any others on the whole periphery, for which either T or U is =0.
Demonstr. I. In puncto (1) eritmφ=45° adeoque T= Rm-1(R√1/2 +Asin(m-1)φ+B/R sin(m-2)φ+ etc. + L/(Rm-2) sinφ); summa vero Asin(m-1)φ+B/R sin(m-2)φ etc. certo non poterit esse maior quam S, adeoque necessario erit minor quam R√1/2: vnde sequitur in hoc puncto valorem ipsius T certo esse positiuum.
Proof. 1. At the point (1) there will bemφ=45°, and so T= Rm-1(R√1/2 +Asin(m-1)φ+B/R sin(m-2)φ+ etc. + L/(Rm-2) sinφ); but indeed the sum Asin(m-1)φ+B/R sin(m-2)φ etc. certainly cannot be greater than S, and so necessarily will be less than R√1/2: whence it follows that at this point the value of T is certainly positive.
By the stronger reason, therefore, T will have a positive value when mφ lies between 45° and 135°, i. e. from point (1) up to (3) the value of T itself will always be positive. By the same reasoning, T will have a positive value everywhere from point (9) up to (11), and in general from any point (8k+1) up to (8k+3), with k denoting any integer whatsoever. In a similar manner, T is everywhere between (5) and (7), between (13) and (15), etc.
and in general between (8k+5) and (8k+7a) it will have a negative value, and so in all these intervals it can nowhere be =0. But since at (3) this value is positive, at (5) negative: necessarily somewhere between (3) and (5) it will be =0; and likewise somewhere between (7) and (9); between (11) and (13), etc., up to the interval between (8m-1) and (1), incl., so that altogether at 2m points one has T=0. Q. E. D.
II. Quod vero praeter haec2m puncta, alia, hac proprietate praedita, non dantur, ita cognoscitur. Quum inter (1) et (3); inter (5) et (7) etc. nulla sint, aliter fieri non posset, vt plura talia puncta exstent, quam si in aliquo interuallo inter (3) et (5), vel inter (7) et (9) etc.
2. But that, indeed, besides these2m points, others endowed with this property
are not given, is recognized thus. Since between (1) and
(3); between (5) and (7) etc. there are none, it could not otherwise happen that
more such points should exist than if in some interval between (3)
and (5), or between (7) and (9) etc.
at a minimum two would lie. Then indeed necessarily in the same interval T would somewhere be a maximum, or a minimum, and so (dT)/(dφ)=0. But (dT)/(dφ)=mRm-2(Rcos mφ+(m-1)/m Acos(m-1)φ+ etc.) and cos mφ between (3) and (5) is always negative and >√1/2. Whence it is easily perceived that in this whole interval (dT)/(dφ) is a negative quantity; and in the same way between (7) and (9) everywhere positive; between (11) and (13) negative, etc., so that in none of these intervals can it be 0, and therefore the supposition cannot stand.
III. Prorsus simili modo demonstratur,U habere valorem negatiuum vbique inter (3) et (5), inter (11) et (13) etc. et generaliter inter (8k+3) et (8k+5); positiuum vero inter (7) et (9), in- ter (15) et (17) etc.
3. In entirely similar fashion it is demonstrated thatU has a negative value everywhere between (3) and (5), between (11) and (13), etc., and generally between (8k+3) and (8k+5); but a positive one between (7) and (9), in- ter (15) and (17), etc.
and generally between (8k+7) and (8k+9). Hence it follows at once that U=0 must occur somewhere between (1) and (3), between (5) and (7), etc., i. e. in 2m points. But in none of these intervals will it be possible that (dT)/(dφ)=0 (which is easily proved in a similar way as above): wherefore more than those 2m points on the periphery of the circle will not be given, at which U=0 occurs. Q. E. T. et Q.
Ceterum ea theorematis pars, secundum quam plura quam 2m puncta non dantur, in quibus T=0, neque plura quam 2m, in quibus U=0, etiam inde demonstrari potest, quod per aequationes T=0, U=0 exhibentur curuae mti ordinis, quales a circulo tamquam curuae secundi ordinis in pluribus quam 2m punctis secari non posse, ex geometria sublimiori constat.
Moreover, that part of the theorem, according to which more than 2m points are not given in which T=0, nor more than 2m in which U=0, can also be demonstrated from this: that by the equations T=0, U=0 there are exhibited curves of the mth order, which by a circle, as a curve of the second order, cannot be cut in more than 2m points, as is established by higher geometry.
Si circulus alius radio maiori quam R ex eodem centro describitur, eodemque modo diuiditur: etiam in hoc inter puncta (3) et (5) iacebit punctum vnum, in quo T=0, itemque inter (7) et (9) etc., perspicieturque facile, quo minus radius huius circuli a radio R differat, eo propius huiusmodi puncta inter (3) et (5) in vtriusque circumferentia sita esse debere. Idem etiam locum habebit, si circulus radio aliquantum minori quam R, attamen maiori quam S√2 et 1 describitur. Ex his nullo negotio intelligitur, circuli radio R descripti circumferentiam in eo puncto inter (3) et (5), vbi T=0, reuera secari ab aliquo ramo lineae primae; idemque valet de reliquis punctis, vbi T=0. Eodem modo patet, circumferentiam circuli huius in omnibus 2m punctis, vbi U=0, ab aliquo ramo lineae secundae secari.
If another circle with a radius greater than R is described from the same center, and is divided in the same manner: likewise in this one between the points (3) and (5) there will lie one point at which T=0, and likewise between (7) and (9), etc.; and it will be easily perceived that, the less the radius of this circle differs from the radius R, by so much the nearer such points between (3) and (5) must lie on the circumference of each. The same will also hold if a circle with a radius somewhat less than R, yet greater than S√2 and 1, is described. From these facts it is understood without any trouble that the circumference of the circle described with radius R, at that point between (3) and (5) where T=0, is indeed cut by some branch of the first line; and the same holds for the remaining points where T=0. In the same way it is clear that the circumference of this circle, at all 2m points where U=0, is cut by some branch of the second line.
These conclusions also can be expressed in the following way: With a circle of appropriate magnitude described from center C, into it there will enter 2m branches of the first line and just as many branches of the second line, and indeed so that pairs of neighboring branches of the first line are separated from one another by some branch of the second line. See fig.
Iam ex hoc situ relatiuo ramorum in circulum intrantium tot modis diuersis deduci potest, intersectionem alicuius rami lineae primae cum ramo lineae secundae intra circulum necessario dari, vt quaenam potissimum methodus prae reliquis eligenda sit, propemodum nesciam. Luculentissima videtur esse haec: Designemus (fig. 2.) punctum peripheriae circuli, vbi a laeua axis parte (quae ipsa est vnus ex 2m ramis lineae primae) secatur, per 0; punctum proximum, vbi ramus lineae secundae intrat, per 1; punctum huic proximum, vbi secundus lineae primae ramus intrat, per 2, et sic porro vsque ad 4m-1, ita vt in quouis puncto numero pari signato ramus lineae secundae in circulum intret, contra ramus lineae secundae in omnibus punctis per numerum imparem expressis.
Now from this relative situation of the branches entering into the circle in so many diverse ways it can be deduced that the intersection of some branch of the first line with a branch of the second line is necessarily given within the circle, so that which method ought preferably to be chosen before the rest I almost do not know. This seems most lucid: Let us designate (fig. 2.) the point of the periphery of the circle, where on the left part of the axis (which itself is one of the 2m branches of the first line) it is cut, by 0; the nearest point, where a branch of the second line enters, by 1; the point next to this, where the second branch of the first line enters, by 2, and so on up to 4m-1, in such a way that at every point marked by an even number a branch of the second line enters into the circle, conversely a branch of the second line in all the points expressed by an odd number.
Now from higher geometry it is established that any algebraic curve (or the individual parts of any algebraic curve, if perchance it is composed of several) is either returning into itself or running out on both sides into infinity; and so, if some branch of an algebraic curve enters a definite region, the same must necessarily somewhere again exit from this region. *10) Hence it is easily concluded that any point marked with an even number (or, for the sake of brevity, any even point) must be joined within the circle by a branch of the first line with another even point; and similarly any point marked with an odd number with another like point by a branch of the second line. Although indeed this connection of pairs of points, according to the character of the function X, can be very diverse, so that in general it cannot be determined, nevertheless it can easily be shown that, whatever it may be, the intersection of the first line with the second line always arises.
Demonstratio huius necessitatis commodissime apagogice repraesentari posse videtur. Scilicet supponamus, iunctionem binorum quorumque punctorum parium, et binorum quorumque punctorum imparium ita adornari posse, vt nulla intersectio rami lineae primae cum ramo lineae secundae inde oriatur. Quoniam axis est pars lineae primae, manifesto punctum 0 cum puncto 2m iunctum erit.
The demonstration of this necessity seems most conveniently able to be represented apagogically. Namely, let us suppose that the joining of each and every pair of even points, and of each and every pair of odd points, can be arranged in such a way that no intersection of a branch of the first line with a branch of the second line arises therefrom. Since the axis is a part of the first line, manifestly the point 0 will be joined with the point 2m.
The point 1 therefore cannot be joined with any point situated beyond the axis, i. e. with any point expressed by a number greater than 2m, otherwise the joining line would necessarily cut the axis. If therefore it is supposed that 1 is joined with the point n, there will be n<2m. By a similar reasoning, if it is posited that 2 is joined with n′, there will be n′<n, because otherwise the branch 2 ... n′ would necessarily cut the branch 1 ... n. From the same cause the point 3 will be joined with some one of the points lying between 4 and n′, and it is clear likewise for 3,4,5 etc.
let [them] be supposed to be joined with n′′, n′′′, n′′′′ etc., n′′′ to lie between 5 and n′′, n′′′′ between 6 and n′′′, etc. Whence it is perspicuous that at length one will be brought to some point h, which is joined with the point h+2, and then the branch which at the point h+1 enters into the circle will necessarily cut the branch joining the points h and h+2. But since one of these two branches will pertain to the first line, the other to the second, it is now manifest that the supposition is contradictory, and so of necessity somewhere an intersection of the first line with the second takes place.
Ceterum haud difficile ex iisdem principiis deduci potest, non solum vnam sed ad minimum m intersectiones lineae primae cum secunda dari, quamquam etiam fieri potest, vt linea prima a pluribus ramis lineae secundae in eodem puncto secetur, in quo casu functio X plures factores aequales habebit. Attamen quum hic sufficiat, vnius intersectionis necessitatem demonstrauisse, fusius huic rei breuitatis caussa non immoror. Ex eadem ratione etiam alias harum linearum proprietates hic vberius non persequor, e. g. intersectionem semper fieri sub angulis rectis; aut si plura crura vtriusque curuae in eodem puncto conueniant, totidem crura lineae primae affore, quot crura lineae secundae, haecque alternatim posita esse, et sub aequalibus angulis se secare etc.
Moreover, it can be deduced not at all with difficulty from the same principles that not only one but at least m intersections of the first line with the second are given, although it can also happen that the first line is cut by several branches of the second line at the same point, in which case the function X will have several equal factors. However, since here it suffices to have demonstrated the necessity of a single intersection, I do not dwell more fully on this matter for the sake of brevity. From the same reasoning I likewise do not pursue here more copiously other properties of these lines, e. g. that the intersection always occurs under right angles; or if more branches of each curve meet at the same point, that there will be as many branches of the first line present as branches of the second line, and that these are placed alternately and cut each other under equal angles, etc.
Denique obseruo, minime impossibile esse, vt demonstratio praecedens, quam hic principiis geometricis superstruxi, etiam in forma mere analytica exhibeatur: sed eam repraesentationem, quam hic explicaui, minus abstractam euadere credidi, verumque neruum probandi hic multo clarius ob oculos poni, quam a demonstratione analytica exspectari possit.
Finally I observe that it is by no means impossible that the preceding demonstration, which I have here superstructured upon geometric principles, also be exhibited in a purely analytic form: but I have judged that that representation, which I have here explained, turns out less abstract, and that the true nerve of proving is here set much more clearly before the eyes, than can be expected from an analytic demonstration.
Coronidis loco adhuc aliam methodum theorema nostrum demonstrandi addigitabo, quae primo aspectu non modo a demonstratione praecedente, sed etiam ab omnibus demonstrationibus reliquis supra enarratis maxime diuersa esse videbitur, et quae nihilominus cum d'Alembertiana, si ad essentiam spectas, proprie eadem est. Cum qua illam comparare, parallelismumque inter vtramque explorare peritis committo, in quorum gratiam vnice subiuncta est.
In place of a coronis I will still append another method of demonstrating our theorem, which at first sight will seem to be not only most different from the preceding demonstration, but also from all the remaining demonstrations narrated above; and which nonetheless, with the d’Alembertian, if you look to the essence, is properly the same. To compare this with that one, and to explore the parallelism between the two, I commit to the experts, for whose sake alone it has been subjoined.
Supra planum figurae 4. relatiue ad axem CG punctumque fixum C descriptas suppono superficiem primam et secundam eodem modo vt supra. Accipe punctum quodcunque in aliquo ramo lineae primae situm siue vbi T=0, ( e. g. quodlibet punctum M in axe iacens), et nisi in hoc etiam U=0, progredere ex hoc puncto in linea prima versus eam partem, versus quam magnitudo absoluta ipsius U decrescit. Si forte in puncto M valor absolutus ipsius U versus vtramque partem decrescit, arbitrarium est, quorsum progrediaris; quid vero faciendum sit, si U versus vtramque partem crescat, statim docebo.
Above the plane of figure 4, relative to the axis CG and the fixed point C, I suppose the first and second surface to be described in the same manner as above. Take any point situated on some branch of the first line, that is where T=0, ( e. g. any point M lying on the axis), and, unless here also U=0, proceed from this point along the first line toward that side toward which the absolute magnitude of U decreases. If by chance at the point M the absolute value of U decreases toward either side, it is arbitrary which way you proceed; but what is to be done if U increases toward either side, I will teach immediately.
It is manifest, therefore, that while you always proceed along the first line, you will necessarily at length come to a point where U=0, or to such a point where the value of U becomes minimal, e. g. the point N. In the former case what was being sought has been found; in the latter, however, it can be demonstrated that at this point several branches of the first line intersect (indeed an even multitude of branches), whose half-branches are so arranged that, if you deflect into any one of them (either this way or that), the value of U still continues to decrease. (The demonstration of this theorem, more prolix than difficult, I ought to suppress for the sake of brevity.) In this branch, therefore, you can proceed again, until U either becomes =0 (as in fig. 4. it happens at P), or again becomes minimal.
Contra hanc demonstrationem obiici posset dubium, annon possibile sit, vt quantumuis longe progrediaris, et quamuis valor ipsius U semper decrescat, tamen haec decrementa continuo tardiora fiant, et nihilominus ille valor limitem aliquem nusquam attingat; quae obiectio responderet quartae in art. 6. Sed haud difficile foret, terminum aliquem assignare, quem simulac transieris, valor ipsius U necessario non modo semper rapidius mutari debeat, sed etiam decrescere non amplius possit, ita vt antequam ad hunc terminum perueneris, necessario valor 0 etiam affuisse debeat. Hoc vero et reliqua, quae in hac demonstratione addigitare tantummodo potui, alia occasione fusius exsequi mihi reseruo.
Against this demonstration a doubt could be raised, whether it is not possible that, however far you proceed, and although the value of U always decreases, nevertheless these decrements become continually slower, and nonetheless that value never reaches any limit; which objection would correspond to the fourth objection in Art. 6. But it would not be difficult to assign some bound such that, as soon as you have passed it, the value of U must of necessity not only change ever more rapidly, but also can no longer decrease, so that before you arrive at this bound, of necessity the value 0 must also already have been present. This, however, and the other points which in this demonstration I have only been able to touch upon, I reserve to set forth more fully on another occasion.
*1) Sub quantitate imaginaria hic semper intelligo quantitatem in forma a+b√-1 contentam, quamdiu b non est =0. In hoc sensu expressio illa semper ab omnibus geometris primae notae accepta est, neque audiendos censeo, qui quantitatem a+b√-1 in eo solo casu imaginarium vocare voluerunt vbi a=0, impossibilem vero quando non sit a=0, quum haec distinctio neque necessaria sit neque vllius vtilitatis. — Si quantitates imaginariae omnino in analysi retineri debent (quod pluribus rationibus consultius videtur, quam ipsas abolere, modo satis solide stabiliantur): necessario tamquam aeque possibiles ac reales spectandae sunt; quamobrem reales et imaginarias sub denominatione communi quantitatum possibilium complecti mallem: contra, impossibilem dicerem quantitatem, quae conditionibus satisfacere debeat, quibus ne imaginariis quidem concessis satisfieri potest, attamen ita, vt phrasis haec idem significet ac si dicas, talem quantitatem in toto magnitudinum ambitu non dari. Hinc vero genus peculiare quantitatum formare, neutiquam concederem.
*1) By an imaginary quantity I here always understand a quantity contained in the form a+b√-1, so long as b is not =0. In this sense that expression has always been accepted by all geometers of the first rank, nor do I judge those to be listened to who wished to call the quantity a+b√-1 imaginary only in the case where a=0, but impossible when a is not =0, since this distinction is neither necessary nor of any utility. — If imaginary quantities ought altogether to be retained in analysis (which for several reasons seems more advisable than to abolish them, provided they are established on a sufficiently solid basis): they must necessarily be regarded as equally possible as real ones; wherefore I would prefer to embrace real and imaginary under the common denomination of possible quantities: on the contrary, I would call a quantity impossible which would have to satisfy conditions to which, even with imaginary quantities admitted, it cannot be satisfied—yet in such a way that this phrase means the same as if you should say that such a quantity is not given anywhere in the whole compass of magnitudes. From this, however, I would by no means allow a peculiar genus of quantities to be formed.
But if someone says that a rectilinear, equilateral, right-angled triangle is impossible, there will be no one to deny it. But if someone should wish to contemplate such an impossible triangle as a new genus of triangles, and to apply other properties of triangles to it, who could hold back laughter? This would be to play with words, or rather to abuse them.
— Although indeed even the foremost mathematicians have often applied truths which manifestly presuppose the possibility of the quantities to which they pertain, also to such as whose possibility was still doubtful; nor would I deny that such licenses for the most part belong to mere form and, as it were, a veil of reasonings, which the keenness of the true geometer can presently penetrate: nevertheless it seems more advisable, and more worthy of the loftiness of that science which is rightly celebrated as the most perfect exemplar of clarity and certainty, either wholly to proscribe such liberties, or at least to employ them more sparingly, nor to use them otherwise, unless where even the less practiced are able to perceive that the matter could have been brought to completion equally rigorously even without their aid, though perhaps less briefly. — Moreover I would by no means deny that the things which I have said here against the abuse of impossibles can in a certain respect be objected also against imaginaries: but the vindication of these, and likewise a fuller exposition of this whole affair, I reserve for another occasion.
*2) Obseruare conuenit, ill. d'Alembert in sua huius demonstrationis expositione considerationes geometricas adhibuisse, atque X tamquam abscissam, x tamquam ordinatam curuae spectauisse (secundum morem omnium geometrarum primae huius saeculi partis, apud quos notio functionum minus usitata erat). Quia vero omnia ipsius ratiocinia, si ad ipsorum essentiam solam respicis, nullis principiis geometricis, sed pure analyticis innituntur, et curua imaginaria, ordinataeque imaginariae expressiones duriores esse lectoremque hodiernum facilius offendere posse videntur, formam repraesentationis mere analyticam hic adhibere malui. Hanc annotationem ideo adieci, ne quis demonstrationem d'Alembertianam ipsam cum hac succinta expositione comparans aliquid essentiale immutatum esse suspicetur.
*2) It is appropriate to observe that the illustrious d’Alembert, in his exposition of this demonstration, employed geometric considerations, and regarded X as the abscissa, x as the ordinate of the curve (according to the custom of all the geometers of the first part of this century, among whom the notion of functions was less usual). But since all his ratiocinations, if you regard their essence alone, rest on no geometric principles but purely analytic ones, and since an imaginary curve and imaginary expressions of the ordinates seem harsher and may more easily offend the modern reader, I have preferred here to employ a purely analytic form of representation. I have added this annotation for this reason, lest anyone, comparing the d’Alembertian demonstration itself with this succinct exposition, suspect that something essential has been altered.
6. for assigning as nearly as possible the sum of other series he employs pp. 441--474. (for the remaining series on pp. 475--478 can truly converge), which, so far as I know, has hitherto been observed by no one. Wherefore it would be greatly to be desired that it be shown lucidly and rigorously why series of this kind, which at first converge very swiftly, then little by little more and more slowly, and finally diverge more and more, nonetheless supply a sum approximately true, provided only that not too many terms be taken, and how far such a sum can safely be regarded as exact?
*4) Tota haec res multum illustrabitur per aliam disquisitionem sub prelo iam sudantem vbi in argumento longe quidem diuerso, nihilominus tamen analogo, liceutiam similem prorsus eodem iure vsurpare potuissem, vt hic in aequationibus ab omnibus analystis factum est. Quamquam vero plurium veritatum demonstrationes adiumento talium fictionum paucis verbis absoluere licuisset, quae absque his perquam difficiles euadunt et subtilissima artificia requirunt, tamen illis omnino abstinere malui, speroque, paucis me satisfacturum fuisse, si analystarum methodum imitatus essem.
*4) This whole matter will be much illuminated by another disquisition
now sweating under the press, where in an argument indeed far different, nonetheless
analogous, I could, by the same right, have usurped a similar license,
as here in equations has been done by all analysts.
Although in truth it would have been permitted to dispatch the demonstrations of more truths with the aid of such
fictions in a few words, which without these
turn out exceedingly difficult and require the most subtle artifices, nevertheless
I preferred to abstain from them altogether, and I hope that I would have satisfied a few,
had I imitated the analysts’ method.
*10) Satis bene certe demonstratum esse videtur, curuam algebraicam neque alicubi subito abrumpi posse (vti e. g. euenit in curua transscendente, cuius aequatio y=1/log x), neque post spiras infinitas in aliquo puncto se quasi perdere (vt spiralis logarithmica), quantumque scio nemo dubium contra rem mouit. Attamen si quis postulat, demonstrationem nullis dubiis obnoxiam alia occasione tradere suscipiam. In casu praesenti vero manifestum est, si aliquis ramus e. g. 2, ex circulo nullibi exiret (fig.
*10) It seems certainly to have been demonstrated quite well that an algebraic curve can neither anywhere be suddenly broken off (as, e. g., happens in a transcendental curve whose equation is y=1/log x), nor, after infinite spirals, as it were lose itself at some point (as the logarithmic spiral), and so far as I know no one has raised a doubt against the matter. Yet if anyone demands it, I will undertake to deliver on another occasion a demonstration subject to no doubts. In the present case, however, it is manifest that, if some branch, e. g. 2, were nowhere to exit from the circle (fig.
3.), that you enter the circle
between 0 and 2, afterwards go around the whole of this branch (which in
the circle’s space ought to lose itself), and at last between 2 and
4 go out of the circle again, so that nowhere on the whole way you fall upon the
first line. But that this is absurd is evident from this, that at the
point where you entered the circle you had the first surface above you, at the egress,
below; wherefore of necessity somewhere you must have fallen upon the first
surface itself, that is, upon a point of the first line. —
Moreover, from this ratiocination resting on the principles of the geometry of position, which
are no less valid than the principles of the geometry of magnitude,
there follows only this: if on some branch of the first line you enter the
circle, you may at another place go out of the circle again, always remaining on the first
line, yet not that your way is a continuous line in the sense in which it is taken in
higher geometry.